Freeman

ARTICLE

The Individual and Majority Rule

NOVEMBER 01, 1974 by RONALD F. COONEY

Mr. Cooney is a free-lance writer in Reno, Nevada.

Belief in majority rule as an eternal verity is so pervasive, devotion to it is so complete and unquestioned, that to offer demurrals is viewed as almost a kind of heresy. What began as a formula of utility has risen by degrees to a national article of faith. One hears constantly reiterated the concept, "majority rule and minority rights," (foremost, apparently, being the right to follow the dictates of the majority). Majority rule has the approval of the majority, and it seems no more need be said. Yet the doubts remain; the nagging questions cry out to be answered. Where is majority rule permissible? Where is it impermissible? What, in short, is its purpose? Does that purpose have limits, and if so, what are they? Can majority rule be reconciled with individual and minority rights?

Underlying these questions is the paradox of every government. Man in a state of nature has maximum freedom limited only by his strength and ability to survive. For protection he establishes a government which, to endure, must limit his freedom. One against the other, liberty and security are in constant conflict. The dilemma becomes acute whenever the forces of safety and order outweigh those of freedom, when even the most trifling human activity is regulated by the State, or conversely, whenever the abuses of liberty bid fair to destroy society, when civil war — in Hobbes’ phrase of "every man against every man" — or anarchy threatens. How to steer between the two extremes, tyranny and anarchy, how to conserve the State for its essential functions and an ultimate of liberty, this is at the bottom of the controversy between the individual and majority rule.

A majority taken collectively may be regarded as a being whose opinions, and most frequently whose interests, are opposed to those of another being, which is styled a minority. If it be admitted that a man, possessing absolute power, may misuse that power by wrongdoing his adversaries, why should a majority not be liable to the same reproach? Men are not apt to change their characters by agglomeration; nor does their patience in the presence of obstacles increase with the consciousness of their strength. And for these reasons I can never willingly invest any number of my fellow-creatures with that unlimited authority which I should refuse to any one of them.

This eloquent passage is taken from Alexis de Tocqueville’s classic Democracy In America. In that work, the author speculated on, among other matters, the phenomenon he called "the despotism of the majority," to which, he felt, popular government was uniquely prone. Tocqueville believed that the potentiality for a democratic tyranny was greater in the United States than anywhere else, for it was the major extant democracy. Ironically, he saw in the very strength and stability of American democratic institutions, in its public opinion, its legislatures, its executive branch, even its courts, the seeds of oppression. These were not a danger to freedom because they were weak, but because they were (and are) so strong, and because they took that strength from a majority of the people. In the face of such total domination, Tocqueville said, a person who felt he had been wronged had no recourse but to the establishments directly or indirectly controlled by the majority. Tocqueville’s concern revolved around the problem of how to preserve liberty where the majority held this immense and irresistible dominance.

Doubts About Democratic Rule

Tocqueville’s apprehension was, in one way, nothing new. Beginning with Plato, political philosophers of an anti-democratic or aristocratic bent had a dread and loathing of popular rule. Plato himself envisioned a perfect state headed by a philosopher king and a carefully chosen and specially trained aristocratic elite, with entrance from the lower classes severely confined. Aristotle after him wanted to alloy as much as possible government of the people with monarchy and aristocracy. But his objections, like those of Plato, were largely theoretical since at that time there were no truly democratic governments worthy of the name. Tocqueville, it must be remembered, was surveying a living democratic republic and sounding, in the name of liberty, a similar cautionary note.

In his discussion of American institutions, Tocqueville possibly had in mind the theories of Jean-Jacques Rousseau. The heart of Rousseau’s radical democracy was the idea of the General Will. More than simply another name for the will of the majority to do whatever it wishes, this general will takes on in Rousseau’s hands the patina of a moral imperative. Infallible, inviolable, completely sovereign and independent, the general will is always a force of the good and the just. Rousseau would allow no disobedience of the general will once its decision had been made. Out of this belief sprang the curious doctrine of compelling a man to be free, of subordinating his will and abiding by the general will even though he may disagree with it. Here, indeed, was democracy —and with a vengeance.

Safeguards Against Tyranny

Although Rousseau had some influence on the Founding Fathers in America, his passion concerning majority rule and majority virtue was not so readily transferable. True, men such as Jefferson and Madison believed in popular government, but they were also realistic enough to see how overweening majority power could quickly become mob-rule. They tried to avoid such an occurrence by building provisions into the machinery of government for the separation and diffusion of power, with authority distributed among three branches. Tocqueville was aware of this, and yet he saw nonetheless a wide latitude remaining for the abuse of power. Later observers of American republican government would make a different argument, remarking that the system of checks and balances and separation of powers made it difficult to pass legislation for the "good" of the community. To what extent those prophecies have been fulfilled (in other words, how well we have been saved from our saviors), is open to debate; one wonders what would be our situation today had not those safeguards existed. If the burden of social legislation is less now than it might be, we owe yet another debt of gratitude to the Founding Fathers.

Besides the foregoing, Tocqueville perceived other difficulties which, while not novel to the American milieu, were characteristic of majoritarian democracies. What happens, for instance when the majority, operating fully within the law, sanctions and puts into effect an unjust law, a law that violates an individual’s personal notions of right and equity, one he cannot obey in good conscience? Does he yield, recognizing the higher morality and purpose of the general will, or does he defy the law, thus affirming the superiority of conscience as a guide? Either the majority is supreme, and hence may enact any laws it deems fitting, or there is a power above the majority and distinct from it, to which the citizen may apply for judgment. What is this power, and who is to take the role of vanquished and of victor in the test of wills? Tocqueville answers this way:

When I refuse to obey an unjust law, I do not contest the right which the majority has of commanding, but I simply appeal from the sovereignty of the people to the sovereignty of mankind. It has been asserted that a people can never entirely out step the boundaries of justice and of reason in those affairs which are more peculiarly its own; and that consequently full power may fearlessly be given to the majority by which it is represented. But this language is that of a slave.

Stated differently, the majority may command but only consonant with reason and justice. If the majority acts to serve the causes of injustice and unreason, the person (or people) so misserved must appeal to mankind at large, to state the case for right and truth in the larger court of humanity. The issue is left to one’s fellow men and their common sense of decency to decide. The type of mentality that would invest in a majority the full capacity for making unjust laws, and an equal capacity to pass on the morality or legality of those laws, is one, Tocqueville firmly believed, more than half way to accepting tyranny.

The Power of Public Opinion

Of less dramatic interest perhaps — but of no less significance — than the collision between the individual conscience and the wrongful decrees of the majority, is the intimate relationship of public opinion and majority rule. The salient difference between Europe and America in this regard is the attitude toward dissenting or unpopular opinions. In Europe, "every sort of religious and political theory may be advocated and propagated abroad," and the man who speaks them has several allies:

If he is unfortunate enough to live under an absolute government, the people is upon his side; if he inhabits a free country, he may find a shelter behind the authority of the throne, if he require one. The aristocratic part of society supports him in some countries, and the democracy in others. But in a nation where democratic institutions exist, organized like those of the United States, there is but one sole authority, one single element of strength and of success, with nothing beyond it.

Tocqueville concedes a certain freedom of thought and expression exists here, but insists it does so at the sufferance of the majority and its "very formidable barriers to the liberty of opinion." To publish and broadcast an opinion outside the pale of majority regulation is to invite "the slights and persecutions of daily obloquy." Tocqueville cites the discrepancy between the methods of monarchical tyranny to prohibit free thought and discussion, and those utilized by the majority in a democratic republic, noting that while "the authority of a king is purely physical… the majority possesses a power which is physical and moral at the same time."

European despots persecuted the body to imprison the soul, but the technique in America is milder, indirect, furtive, and subtle. The majority disciplines unpopular opinions — meaning those it does not share — by narrowing the opportunity for their expression, and by stifling, through group-pressure, the will that inspires them. Tocqueville lived too early to witness the horror of modern totalitarian states, which employ slave-labor camps and indoctrination, subjugating at once the body and the mind.

Tocqueville observes the equality of conditions in America, and advances the theory that such equality leads to a centralization of power in the State. So long as inequality is the rule, scattered instances of privilege engender little popular indignation. But when equality prevails, "the slightest dissimilarity is odious." Under a monarchy, the people look to the king, as the head of the State, to rectify the inequity. Under a democracy, the people look directly to the State itself, the rationale being, "that each of them thinks that he strips his equals of the prerogative which he concedes to the crown." Considering the power thus rendered, it is not so unusual that the State began to enforce equality from above, prompting Tocqueville to say: "The American people would rather be equal in slavery than unequal in freedom."

"Benign Despotism"

Given this extreme equality, and given too this ever-expanding State-power, the chances for a form of despotism — one new in the world — are greatly enhanced. Unlike the tyrannies of old, a democratic-egalitarian dictatorship would wear a benign aspect. It would order the life of the people for their benefit; it would have their interests in mind at all times. While it maintained an outward semblance of freedom, "under the wing of the sovereignty of the people," it would quietly —and without resort to the rack or thumbscrews — extend its authority into every corner of human life, regulating, managing, and dictating each activity, important and minor alike. The new dispensation "renders the exercise of the free agency of men less useful and less frequent," the end result being that "each nation is reduced to be nothing better than a flock of timid and industrious animals, of which the government is the shepherd." A chilling prospect to contemplate this is, and none the less so since it describes precisely the state of America today — or at the very least the state to which it is tending.

As Tocqueville realized in his diagnosis of the democratic malady, the question of the individual and majority rule cannot be separated from the more pertinent subject of the individual and the State. One can hardly speak of limiting the power of the majority without implying a restriction on the State’s domain, for in a democracy the two are inseparably fused. The majority is the State and the State is the majority. And, like the confusion surrounding the proper sphere of the State, there is an equally gross misconception with respect to what majority rule is meant to do, what it may do, and what it may not do. It is, in fact, a utilitarian principle intended to expedite the operation of government, to aid in the transfer of the reins of power, and to give a raw consensus for proposed legislation. It is not a carte blanche for one transiently ascendant group to violate the rights of any minority or individual. At most, it is supreme in those matters that are the necessary and correct duties of the State, those which the State alone can discharge, and more especially in those whose design is the defense and survival, in freedom, of the nation.

A Legacy to Keep

Perhaps it will be argued, in response to the preceding, that if the warrants of the Bill of Rights remain intact, freedom will be amply protected, and consequently all this talk of the dangers of majority rule is so much supererogation. The intention here is to find fault neither with the Bill of Rights nor with the men who gave us our government. The Founding Fathers were wise and prescient men who believed in limited government, in Jefferson’s oft-quoted but still resonant words, "the government which governs best governs least." Having themselves escaped the grip of monarchical tyranny, they were cognizant also of the possibility of a democratic tyranny arising in America. They knew a despotism bearing the imprimatur of a numerical majority was a despotism still, and that sheer weight of numbers sanctified nothing. To avert both types of oppression, by one man or by many men, was the aim of the Bill of Rights.

But we have witnessed how even the Bill of Rights may be turned against freedom, as in the Dred Scott case where the Fifth Amendment was used to keep millions of blacks in bondage, and how far, especially in the last forty years, government can go while remaining, on the surface, faithful to Constitutional guarantees (Tocqueville’s comment concerning the "outward forms of freedom" has a piercing aptness here). And it could be that placing restraints on the State is not a matter for legislation at all but an attitude of mind which must grow out of the people themselves. The Founding Fathers had this attitude, but somehow the legacy has been lost.

It may be that the impulse to bestow absolute supremacy upon a majority, like the related urge to confer unrestricted power upon the State, admits of no easy remedy. It is too deeply rooted in the common conviction that because today government is conceived to be a force for good, it can be entrusted with power it will not use for evil tomorrow; that because the majority now shares this conception, it will always share it; that because ours is a democracy and the majority chooses our leaders, it will never choose one who will misuse the power once given with such good faith and with such fond hope, so freely and so willingly.   

ASSOCIATED ISSUE

November 1974

comments powered by Disqus

EMAIL UPDATES

* indicates required

CURRENT ISSUE

October 2014

Heavily-armed police and their supporters will tell you they need all those armored trucks and heavy guns. It's a dangerous job, not least because Americans have so many guns. But the numbers just don't support these claims: Policing is safer than ever--and it's safer than a lot of common jobs by comparison. Daniel Bier has the analysis. Plus, Iain Murray and Wendy McElroy look at how the Feds are recruiting more and more Americans to do their policework for them.
Download Free PDF

PAST ISSUES

SUBSCRIBE

RENEW YOUR SUBSCRIPTION