Freeman

ARTICLE

Book Review: The God of the Machine by Isabel Paterson Introduction by Stephen Cox

SEPTEMBER 01, 1994 by JOHN ATTARIAN

Transaction Publishers, Rutgers-the State University, New Brunswick, NJ 08903, 1993 • 308 + lvii pages • $21.95 paperback

First published in 1943, when voices raised in defense of freedom were few, The God of the Machine, “a study of the flow of energy and the nature of government as mechanism,” is both an ambitious and original interpretation of history and a brilliant defense of individual liberty.

For Paterson, “Energy is the medium of life.” It cannot be created, but it can be converted into useful forms, by the creative, acting individual. “In the social organization, man is the dynamo, in his productive capacity . . . . He has a faculty for which no equivalent is found in the processes of inanimate nature. He is self-starting, and he can inhibit himself” (her italics). Man is “self-starting and self-acting.” Paterson’s conception resembles the “acting person” at the core of Pope John Paul’s endorsement of the free economy.

With individuals as dynamos, economic life is an energy flow; Paterson uses an electrical circuit as a metaphor for the circular flow of production and exchange. For energy to flow, certain institutions are appropriate. “Personal liberty is the precondition of the release of energy. Private property is the inductor which initiates the flow.” Paterson contrasts the “Society of Contract” with the “Society of Status.” Grounded in awareness of the individual’s God-given, inalienable right to life, the former society leaves people free to act, bargain freely, and produce, hence is a prerequisite for prosperity. In the latter, people have no rights, and exist on sufferance, making the Society of Status at odds with reality. “The vital functions of a living creature do not wait on permission; and unless a person is already able to act of his own motion, he cannot obey a command.” Hence the Society of Status is “geared to a lower potential of energy than the Society of Contract,” resulting in lower economic performance.

Some government is necessary. “Initiative is life itself. Complete inhibition is death. Yet a living creature incapable of inhibiting itself would speedily destroy itself.” Limited government, enforcing rights, protecting producers from predators so energy may circulate, acts as the inhibitor—analogous to brakes and governors, which “are set to operate only if the motor and transmission goes wrong . . . . these are not preventive controls, but corrective; they are not primary but secondary,” e.g., contract laws. Excessive government drains too much energy from the circuit, so not enough gets through to resume the flow, resulting in economic decline; it may even short-circuit the economy altogether.

Three great ideas brought humanity to the Society of Contract: science, law, and Christianity’s stress on the individual. They came together in our Constitution, which Paterson interprets brilliantly as a great energy-liberator, albeit flawed by the compromise allowing slavery. But the 14th-18th Amendments disastrously concentrated power in the national government.

Paterson explains money and credit with enviable clarity, and brilliantly explodes the fiat money fallacy. “flit is said that anything will do for money, as long as people accept it, let it be asked, why will not people accept ‘anything?’ Offer the man who says ‘anything will do for money,’ a handful of pebbles in payment of a debt.” As for inflating bad debt away: “If twenty million bushels of wheat were contracted for, and only ten million bushels existed, there really would not be enough wheat to fulfill the contract; but in that case, nobody would argue that there must be something wrong with wheat as a commodity; much less that the situation could be remedied by calling half a bushel of wheat a bushel . . . . But that is what is done with money in a crisis.”

Indeed, one of Paterson’s many strengths is her demolition of so much collectivist nonsense: “the greatest good for the greatest number,” majority rule,”production for use and not for profit” (“as if there could be any profit if the product were not used”), public ownership, “all property is theft” (“Theft presupposes rightful ownership. An object must be property before [her italics] it can be stolen.”), and so on.

Her chapter “The Humanitarian With the Guillotine” tackles one of the worst fallacies: coercive compassion. While suffering is part of existence, successful life is the norm. “Therefore it cannot be supposed that the producer exists only for the sake of the nonproducer, the well for the sake of the ill, the competent for the sake of the incompetent; nor any person merely for the sake of another.” Paterson upholds voluntary charity by religions, which “have always recognized the conditions of the natural order,” and calls for meeting the moral obligation of charity “out of the producer’s surplus. That is, they make it secondary to production,” (her italics) since nothing can be given unless produced. And, recognizing the rights of producers, they obtain money by asking, not commanding.

Humanitarians, however, wish to command producers, so as to take credit for production. Moreover:

If the primary objective of the philanthropist, his justification for living, is to help others, his ultimate good requires that others shall be in want [her italics]. His happiness is the obverse of their misery . . . . The humanitarian wishes to be a prime mover in the lives of others. He cannot admit either the divine or the natural order, by which men have the power to help themselves. The humanitarian puts himself in the place of God.

This courageous chapter alone is worth the price of the book. It should be read by everyone, especially welfare statists.

Paterson’s electrical metaphors are brilliant, but exasperating in their inadequate articulation. The latter flows from the book’s major flaw: deficient organization, a forgivable failing in a pioneering work but well-nigh crippling. Since her metaphors are novel and demanding, she should have opened by presenting and explaining her frame of reference, instead of scattering it throughout the text. As it is, the reader must divine her framework in dribs and drabs by piecemeal epiphanies.

Nonetheless, The God of the Machine is magnificent. It deserves and richly repays the careful reading it requires. []

John Attarian is a free-lance writer in Ann Arbor. Michigan, with a Ph.D. in economics.

ASSOCIATED ISSUE

September 1994

comments powered by Disqus

EMAIL UPDATES

* indicates required

CURRENT ISSUE

October 2014

Heavily-armed police and their supporters will tell you they need all those armored trucks and heavy guns. It's a dangerous job, not least because Americans have so many guns. But the numbers just don't support these claims: Policing is safer than ever--and it's safer than a lot of common jobs by comparison. Daniel Bier has the analysis. Plus, Iain Murray and Wendy McElroy look at how the Feds are recruiting more and more Americans to do their policework for them.
Download Free PDF

PAST ISSUES

SUBSCRIBE

RENEW YOUR SUBSCRIPTION