Freeman

ARTICLE

Thielicke on the Modern Welfare State

The Responsibility of Love Cannot Be Transferred

AUGUST 01, 1996 by DANIEL WALKER

Filed Under : Welfare State

Mr. Walker is an attorney in private practice in Tallahassee, Florida.

Helmut Thielicke was a leading Christian theologian of the post-World War II era. Early in his career, Thielicke was removed from his teaching position at the University of Heidelberg because of his criticism of the Nazi regime. Late in the war, he was allowed to preach and informally teach in Stuttgart. Thielicke’s lectures and sermons were privately (and illegally) published, bringing a Christian message to thousands of people.

After the war, Thielicke held high positions at the universities of Tubingen and Hamburg, and several published collections of his sermons brought him acclaim in the English-speaking world. What established him as a leading theologian, however, were two multi-volume works: The Evangelical Faith and Theological Ethics.

In Theological Ethics, Thielicke addressed the dangers of governmental paternalism. While Thielicke did accept a role for government in providing a “safety net” for its citizens, he expressed deep alarm at the reach and effects of the modern welfare state.

Thielicke defined the “rationalization” of the welfare state’s process as “organizing the effort in such a way that a maximum of production is achieved with a minimum of expenditure,” thus infusing impersonalization into the welfare process and depersonalizing the participants. Direct, personal caring would be reduced to a minimum, “and even then the final stage will be a welfare office desk or the home mailbox.”[1] Forms, computers, and adding machines—not individual love of one’s neighbor—would drive the process.

The greater the reliance of the welfare-state machinery upon the depersonalization of givers and recipients, the greater the effects. Unlike many theologians, who improperly interpret the New Testament as a manifesto for “compassion” by force of government, Thielicke recognized the undesirable consequences, economic and personal, of the modern welfare state.

Individual Initiative and the Burgeoning Welfare State

External consequences of the growing welfare state would be an increasing tax burden, decreased investment in the means of production, and a strain on credit; a further danger was that of welfare “benefits” threatening “to become the equivalent of a normal wage” or, even where not, “a temptation . . . for people to quit their job, justify their action on other grounds, and make up the loss in income by doing part-time work on the side. All this leads to chaotic tendencies in the labor market.”

Internal, personal consequences of the rationalized welfare state also were serious. As the modern welfare state embraces more “duties,” it “not only reduces individual initiative but also kindles suspicion of the welfare work of other groups” and “demands that all activities which impinge upon its monopoly must first receive official authorization.” While American governments do not have a monopoly on providing welfare services, Thielicke’s concern is valid; think of charitable organizations having to obtain 501(c)(3) recognition from the Internal Revenue Service before donors’ contributions can be used to reduce individual tax liabilities assessed by the government.

State Welfare versus Genuine Caring

Of deep concern to Thielicke was the inner consequence where “welfare becomes the object of a `claim’: In time of need, when I cannot care for myself, I claim to have a right to be cared for; the state is obliged to assist me whether or not I act or am capable of acting to help myself.” As Thielicke said, “welfare is thus transferred from the ethical to the legal plane.”

Anticipating more contemporary arguments, Thielicke noted that supporters of welfare “rights” would emphasize the alleged “degrading” nature of people having to rely upon private charity, of being a mere object of benefactors’ good will—thus violating the recipients’ “dignity.”

Thielicke found that argument “meretricious,” making “a false distinction between welfare as a legal act regulated by the state and welfare as the function of private, improvising love.” Genuine Christian love of one’s neighbor does not degrade the recipient of aid. Genuine caring for another person is not mechanical, nor is it a “subject-object relation between giver and recipient,” but it is a partnership. Within the Christian context, “the giver knows that he is one who, in relation to God, receives without merit, and who must therefore act towards his neighbor as God has acted toward him.” This is a dignity far different than that contemplated by supporters of the modern welfare state.

For Thielicke, a society in which the government “provides in principle for every kind of disability and the helplessness of old age” would alter “fatefully the relationship between the generations.” Families with sufficient financial strength should care for family members who need help.

Look at America now; older middle-income Americans are encouraged to divest themselves of their assets in order to qualify for Medicaid so that taxpayers at large must subsidize the costs of warehousing the artificially impoverished in nursing homes—in the name of “independent living” and “not being a burden to the children.” Thielicke said that such a welfare apparatus for caring “would make parenthood a temporary function: When the function is fulfilled, parents simply step down and enter another sphere of existence.” So it seems today in the United States.

Again anticipating contemporary battles, Thielicke asserted that opportunities should be present for people to plan and “pay in advance for later pensions and other benefits (medical benefits, etc.).” Aside from the economic advantages to be gained by Individual Retirement Accounts, medical savings accounts, and other similar measures, the greatest benefit from such planning opportunities is that citizens can be active participants in the continuity of their lives rather than being mere passive recipients of whatever favors are doled out by a particular government. Genuine welfare depends upon personal involvement, but “the radical welfare state aims at state pensions for all citizens without distinction, irrespective of need or achievement. . . . It has become instead the welfare robot, devoid of any personal features at all.” Does any of this ring true, in light of talk about welfare state recipients being given ATM-like cards to “access” their government benefits?

Ultimately, Thielicke characterized the State as an “emergency order” to which “we should commit to the state, not everything we can, but only what we must. . . . [T]he state should give up as many tasks as possible and commit them to other agencies.”

Thielicke was not fooled by those who would equate “compassion” with a pervasive welfare state and greater taxes. Those who “farm out to the machinery of the state all care of the needy” are “refusing to be human toward a fellow human being.” Delegating a personal moral responsibility to a “robot” shows a lack of involvement in others’ lives. The modern welfare state cannot be a substitute for proper love of one’s neighbor. Even if the welfare state “worked,” was efficient, and delivered to or on behalf of recipients most of each dollar allocated for welfare—it still would do damage.

How? Why?

According to Thielicke, “The responsibility of love cannot be transferred. Love that is hidden away in some mechanical apparatus `gains me nothing.’ And when I am without love I myself `am nothing.’ (I Cor. 13:2). The perfection of the machinery can actually deliver up the person to nothingness.”

Those who would invoke Christian compassion in defense of the modern welfare state would be wise to consider the warnings of Helmut Thielicke. He looked beyond superficial sentiment and good intentions associated with government-driven caring, and found tremendous dangers awaiting the society that diminishes the personal dimension of caring for one’s neighbor in exchange for a mechanical state of “social justice.”


1.   Helmut Thielicke, Theological Ethics (Grand Rapids, Mich.: Eerdmans, 1979), vol. II, p. 301. Subsequent quotations are from the same volume, pp. 302-317.

ASSOCIATED ISSUE

August 1996

comments powered by Disqus

EMAIL UPDATES

* indicates required

CURRENT ISSUE

December 2014

Unfortunately, educating people about phenomena that are counterintuitive, not-so-easy to remember, and suggest our individual lack of human control (for starters) can seem like an uphill battle in the war of ideas. So we sally forth into a kind of wilderness, an economic fairyland. We are myth busters in a world where people crave myths more than reality. Why do they so readily embrace untruth? Primarily because the immediate costs of doing so are so low and the psychic benefits are so high.
Download Free PDF

PAST ISSUES

SUBSCRIBE

RENEW YOUR SUBSCRIPTION

Essential Works from FEE

Economics in One Lesson (full text)

By HENRY HAZLITT

The full text of Hazlitt's famed primer on economic principles: read this first!


By FREDERIC BASTIAT

Frederic Bastiat's timeless defense of liberty for all. Once read and understood, nothing ever looks the same.


By F. A. HAYEK

There can be little doubt that man owes some of his greatest suc­cesses in the past to the fact that he has not been able to control so­cial life.


By JEFFREY A. TUCKER

Leonard Read took the lessons of entrepreneurship with him when he started his ideological venture.


By LEONARD E. READ

No one knows how to make a pencil: Leonard Read's classic (Audio, HTML, and PDF)